Samkhya
Philosophy - An overview
By Swami Tapasyananda
What is Kapilopadesha?
The Bhagavata Purana is
essentially a text on Bhakti or love of God. It proudly
proclaims its exclusive concern with Bhakti thus: ‘In
other scriptural texts, Hari, the eraser of the evils
of Kali and the Lord of all, is not described again and again with such
devotional exuberance as is done in this Text, the Bhagavata.
Through innumerable narratives, in fact through every word in it, the one topic
highlighted is the Bhagawan, the One embracing all that
exists’ (XII.12.65). Again it says in another context, referring to the accounts
given in it of the royal dynasties and to the other narratives, historical or otherwise,
described in it: ‘0 great King! I have narrated to you these stories of great men,
who after spreading their fame in the world have died and disappeared, only to generate
in you discriminative wisdom and spiritual enlightenment. They form only a literary
device to drive home those great lessons, and are not the ultimate Truth in themselves.
Then, as for that ultimate Truth, it is this: Those who aspire to have pure and
undiluted devotion to
Krishna
should constantly hear about His sin-destroying acts and excellences sung or chanted
or discoursed upon by great devotees. Let them hear that alone always’ (XII.3.14-15).
The topic of God-love as treated in the Bhagavata takes
two main forms that may be called as Jnana-bhakti and
Bhava-bhakti. Jnana-bhakti
or love based on a vivid awareness of Divine majesties makes one sink into Him in
utter self-surrender and become one with His being through His grace.
Bhava-bhakti or sentimental devotion, on the other hand, is based on
sense of loving intimacy with Him, analogous to various forms of loving human relationships.
It does not seek dissolution in Him but eternal service to Him. While all the narratives
of the Bhagavata are meant to illustrate God-love in
both these aspects, this is done more directly through the great hymns and discourses
with which the narratives are interspersed. Among these discourses the most comprehensive
ones are Sri Krishna’s sermon to Uddhava in the eleventh
Skandha and Kapila’s sermon
to Dévahuti, his mother, in the third
Skandha.
The latter sermon, forming the theme of this book, is as charming in its setting
as it is in the profundity of the teachings it sets forth. A son instructing his
mother in Brahma-vidya is no less romantic than a husband
doing the same with his wife in the great Brihadaranyaka
episode of Yajnavalkya imparting the knowledge of Brahman
to his wife Maitreyi. Kapila,
according to Hindu tradition, is an incarnation of Mahavishnu.
His father was Kardama Prajapati
and mother, Devahuti, the daughter of
Svayambhuva Manu. Kardama was a great ascetic,
but he had been commissioned by his father Brahma to propagate the species in those
early days of the world. So when Manu Svayambhuva, seeking
a suitable husband for his daughter Devahuti, approached
him, he accepted that offer of a bride and thus he married Devahuti
on the stipulation that after the ninth child was born, he would abandon home to
resume his ascetic life. He bad nine daughters by
Devahuti. In due course
he arranged for their marriage.
After having thus fulfilled his duties, he was, according to the old stipulation,
about to go forth as a wandering ascetic. Thereupon, Devahuti
prayed to him that he should stay on with her for sometime more, until she had a
boy born. Kardama agreed, and soon the male child came.
That was Kapila.
Kardama was now free to go forth as a wandering ascetic
but before he did so, he approached his son, about whose divinity he already knew,
and recited a hymn in his praise. As a parting message the son told the father as
follows: ‘... I have fulfilled my promise of being born as your son. The object
of this incarnation of mine is to distinguish and enumerate the various categories
in order that Truth seekers may be enabled to realize the Atman. Distinguishing
it from the perishable body-mind combination with which It
is confused. ....(111.24.35-37).
Kapila’s birth had been heralded by Divine visions to
his parents, intimating that their son was none other than Mahavishnu
incarnated to teach mankind the science of the Spirit. Fully enlightened as he was
at his very birth, Kapila also wanted to leave hearth
and home very early in life, but his mother Devahuti
prayed to him that he should do so only after imparting the Saving Knowledge to
her. Accordingly Kapila stayed back and began to teach
her this recondite subject. We get Kapila’s sermons
to his mother Devahuti, interspersed with her questions,
in Chapters 25 to 33 of the third Skandha of the Bhagavata Purana.
A Puzzling Philosophical Milieu.
At the start itself his teaching is announced as follows by Shaunaka:
‘In order to reveal the knowledge of the Atman to men, the Lord, though in Himself
birthless, embodied Himself by the power of His own
Maya, as Kapila, the propounder
of the doctrine of Samkhya.’ For a student of Indian
philosophy, Samkhya is known as an atheistic doctrine,
and it will be a matter of astonishment for him to be told that it required a Divine
Incarnation to propound such a godless philosophy. A great Vedantic
Acharya like Shankara has
inveighed against the Samkhya with all his logical acumen
as his Pradhana-malla (principal opponent) in his commentary
on the Brahma Sutras. But the student’s astonishment will be greater still to note
that the same Acharya is not much concerned in his commentary
on the Gita when
Sri Krishna calls his doctrine Samkhya in five places
(11.39; 111.3; V.4-5; XIII.24 and XVIIL13) and describes it as Vedanta only in one
place (V.15). Commenting on the line ‘esa
te abhihita
samkhye’ (11.39), he interprets ‘samkhye’
as ‘paramartha-vastu-visaye’, i.e. ‘in regard to the
Supreme Truth’. In other words, he takes the word ‘Samkhya’
to mean only ‘metaphysical reality’, and not as a reference to the atheistic Samkhya system attributed to Kapila.
Yet when he comments on ‘procyate guna-samkhyane’,
i.e. ‘it is said in the enumeration of Gunas’ (XVIII.
19), he interprets ‘guna-samkhyana’ as a reference to
Kapila’s system, meaning the classical
Samkhya of the Samkhya Karika,
which is atheistic. Realizing the inconsistency of it perhaps, he immediately adds,
‘This Shastra is a valid source of knowledge about the
constituents (Gunas) and the Jivas
who experience. Though it contradicts in respect of the non-duality of the metaphysically
Real or Brahman, the followers of Kapila
are adepts as regards constituents and their operation.’ Without feeling the least
puzzled, he unhesitatingly accepts
Krishna’s statement in Vibhuti
Yoga that among Siddhas (perfect men),
he is Muni Kapila (X.26).
How could he without any comment accept wholeheartedly an atheistic philosopher
as the greatest of Siddhas or perfect men?
The same puzzle will be felt by any one studying this treatise
Kapilopadesha, wherein Kapila is described
as an Incarnation of Mahavishnu and a teacher of a noble
doctrine of God-love and Knowledge. It will be all the more so, if he happens also
to be a student of the six systems of Indian philosophy wherein the
Samkhya is also included. That system, as depicted there, is based on
Ishwarakrishna’s Samkhya
Karika, and is noted for its uncompromising dualistic
pluralism, absolute realism, and pronounced atheism. As knowledge of this classical
Samkhya will be helpful in understanding the relevancy
of the Bhagavata Samkhya
of Kapila, we shall now deal with the former in brief,
and also with what preceded it, namely, the pre-classical Samkhya.
Classical samkhya: prakriti
and purusha
The Samkhya system depicts reality as two mutually opposed
categories, the subjective and the objective, each of them self-subsisting, eternal,
and underivable from the other. This doctrine of uncompromising
dualism is historically a reaction to the monistic absolutism of the early Upanishads
like the Brihadaranyaka. The subject is called Purusha, a term already familiar from the time of the
Purusha-sukta, but conveying an entirely different meaning
in the Samkhyan context. The Purusha
of the Samkhya is a countless multiplicity of individual
centres of pure consciousness, without capacity for
any kind of work. He is always a subject, an enjoyer, and a witness, but never an
actor. Though individual, each Purusha is
Vibhu or all-pervading, but non-contactual
with other Purushas and therefore Kevala
(alone). Neither the effect nor the cause of anything, the Purusha
is attributeless and partless.
The existence of such centres of intelligence is inferable,
as nature (Prakriti), its insentient opposite, is found
purposive in functioning, and purposiveness implies
intelligence somewhere.
As opposed to the Purusha, the Subjective
Eternal, is Prakriti, the Objective Eternal.
Prakriti means the unevolved
indiscrete matrix of all (the Avyakrita), inferred as
the cause of all the experienced effect conditions or evolutes (the
Vikritis) potential in it. It is known by various names as
Pradhana (the first category), Avyakta
(indiscrete), etc. Though uncaused, eternal, partless,
and omnipresent like the Purusha, it is just his opposite
in all other respects. It is single,’ insentient, and objective. Productivity or
evolution into a multiplicity is its most important feature and function. It manifests,
as its evolutes (Vikritis), the twenty three categories,
which form the basic substances of which the manifested universe is composed. These
evolutes, which are of the nature of effects, are not newly generated but only brought
into manifestation from a preexisting causal condition. For the effect is always
contained in the cause in an indiscrete state, and evolution means only the manifestation
of the already existing entity and not production of anything new (Satkarya-vada).
The Gunas
The productivity or dynamism of Prakriti is born of
the Gunas—Sattva, Rajas
and Tamas-which form its very stuff. The concept of
Gunas is fundamental to the Samkhya
philosophy, and the meaning of the word in the Samkhyan
context differs widely from its usually understood meanings like attribute, a secondary
entity, rope, etc. In the Samkhya,
Gunas form both substance and attribute. To make any absolute difference
between them is an unrealistic abstraction. It is sometimes said that they are the
constituents or component factors of Prakriti, which
is misleading, as it gives the idea that Prakriti is
either a compound or a receptacle of the Gunas, while
actually Prakriti is itself the Gunas,
it being in an ontological identity with them. It may then be asked why the concept
of the Gunas is introduced at all except it
be for confusing the issues? The Samkhya
replies: ‘The Prakriti works though the
Gunas - avyaktam pravartate
trigunatah’ (Karika 16).
It may therefore be said that the Gunas are the ‘functional
modes’ or ‘dispositions’ of Prakriti.
Sattva makes for ‘existence’ or ‘beingness’
of Prakriti, thus asserting the absolute realism o the
Samkhya. Rajas is what makes
for ‘change-in-itself’. Prakriti is Rajas, and not possessed
of it or qualified by it. It asserts the inherent dynamism of Prakriti,
just as Sattva, its inherent existentialness.
Tamas is that which ‘restrains annihilation through
change’, Niyamyata. It is the inherent capacity to restrain
the process of change and preserve the identity. Therefore, by means of these dispositions,
Prakriti exists (Sattva);
existing, it changes (Rajas); and through changing, retains itself (Tamts).
These three factors involve each other mutually or reciprocally, and therefore form
only the three ‘operational modes’ of Prakriti. To make
any absolute ontological distinction among them as when we call them constituents
of Prakriti, will be wrong, though one may do so as
an intellectual abstraction for purposes of study. They are not to be thought of
as three quantities balancing themselves in Samyavastha
(state of devolution and equilibrium), or as one or another dominating the rest
and upsetting the equilibrium into the state of Vikriti
(evolution and productivity). They are the functional forces of
Prakriti, each convertible into others and each including in it elements
of the others. When they become equally operative, in that state of equilibrium
they are called Prakriti or the Avyakta
(unevolved), and when in the proximity of
Purusha the equilibrium of forces is lost, the Prakriti
becomes Vyakta (the evolved).
These three forces, though not qualities in themselves, exhibit in their operative
state of productivity, qualities through which they are recognized.
Sattva exhibits the physical characteristics of buoyancy and illumination,
and the psychological characteristics of pleasure, peace and intelligence. Rajas
or change-in-itself is expressed as stimulation and movement, and as the psychological
characteristics of qualities like pain and passion. Tamas
expresses as the physical characteristics of weight, resistance, inertia, and darkness,
and as the psychological expressions like despondency, sloth, ignorance, etc. The
Gunas are therefore recognized through their characteristic
expressions as evolutes and qualities.
The Functioning of the Gunas
The Gunas are thus the inherent mechanism of
Prakriti which keeps it ever dynamic (Rajas), but also ever existent
(Sattva) and ever sustained (Tamas)
too. When the dynamism is inwardly operative, Prakriti
is in a state of balance (Samyavastha) and is called
Avyakrita or Avyakta (indiscrete
and unevolved). When the dynamism is working outwardly,
Prakriti becomes Vyakta
or evolved into categories, each category producing the succeeding category or sets
of categories. In other systems of Indian philosophy, most of which accept the doctrine
of Gunas and Prakriti, there
is, unlike in the Samkhya, a place for
Ishwara, a God, whose will directs the mechanism of Prakriti
to evolve into the universe and to dissolve into the primordial condition in periods
of cycles called Srishti and Pralaya.
Classical Samkhya however does not approach the problem
so much from a cosmological point of view as from the psychological. No God is recognized,
as it is an unnecessary presumption according to the classical
Samkhya. Purushas, the Subjective Eternals,
are centres of consciousness. Proximate to them is the
insentient but inherently dynamic Prakriti, the Objective
Eternal. According to the classical Samkhya, these two
ultimates are sufficient to understand evolution. There
is no need for a super-category called Ishwara (God).
The dynamism of Prakriti is not a purposeless mechanical
movement. It becomes operative outwardly due to the proximity of the
Purusha and for serving the purpose of the Purusha.
The Purusha is always separate and different from the
Prakriti, but proximity, which is left unexplained,
is assumed in order to account for the state of human existence which, being subject
to births, deaths, and the intervening experiences, is dominated by suffering. The
individual Purushas, who are by nature
centres of pure consciousness only, get involved with Prakriti
through proximity and the mutual transference of attributes and functions that take
place consequently. Though entirely different from each other, the
Purusha and Prakriti in union through proximity
and mutual transference of attributes by reflection, bring into being the
Jiva who is subject to suffering and seeks freedom from the same.
To explain this union between Prakriti and
Purusha even when they are separate by nature, the Samkhya
philosophers use an analogy. A blind man and a lame man come together. The lame
one, by getting on the blind one, can move purposefully towards a destination. The
intelligent but inactive Purusha is like the motionless
but seeing lame man, and Prakriti, like the moving but
sightless blind man. In combination they can subserve
an individual or a common purpose - a Purushartha. The Samkhya does
not explain why and when this union by proximity between these two entirely different
entities came about. It is satisfied to point out that this is the
predicamnt in which man finds himself and which necessitates philosophical
enquiry. But the mechanism of this linking is explained. It is through the reflection
of the Purusha in Buddhi,
the first evolute of Prakriti.
Being purely Sattvika, the Buddhi
is capable of reflecting the pure intelligence that the Purusha
is. The Purusha, because of this link or reflection
known technically as Linga, falsely identifies himself
with all the movements of the reflections of Prakriti,
and the insentient Prakriti, which receives the reflection
of the Purusha, appears as an intelligent and active
body-mind. The Buddhi with the reflection is the subtle
body which is involved in the cycle of births and deaths, receiving new bodies with
each physical death. This involvement stops only when the Purusha
realizes his separateness from Prakriti with which he
has falsely been conceiving himself to be one, the link in this identification being
the reflection.
The Twenty-four Categories
Now the Samkhya comes forward to liberate the
Purusha from this predicament by imparting philosophic wisdom through
the analysis of man and his environment, into the various categories of which they
are constituted. The very meaning of the word ‘Samkhya’
implies these two functions. Samkhya is interpreted
as the pursuit of a discriminative wisdom. Derived from the root ‘Khya’,
enumeration, together with the prefix ‘Sam’, it imparts wisdom through the analysis
and enumeration of experience into the categories constituting it. The two basic
self- existent categories, as we have already shown, are the Purusha
and the Prakriti, the subjective factor of consciousness,
and the objective factor experienced by consciousness. The Purusha,
being inactive and unproductive, always remains as he is, and brings out nothing
of himself. But Prakriti, being the dynamic productive
factor evolves into twenty-three categories when the equilibrium of the
Gunas (the Samyavastha) is lost due to the
proximity of the Purusha. Prakriti
does so for fulfilling the purpose of the Purusha, namely,
to effect his release from her own wiles.
The categories are not produced all at a time, but evolved, each one coming out
of the previously evolved one. They are not generated but evolved in the sense that
the term is understood in the light of the Satkarya-vada
(the theory of the previous existence of the effect). The first
evolute to emerge is Buddhi (intellect),
and out of it Ahamkara (I-sense) having three bifurcations
resulting from the three Gunas of Prakriti
- Sattva, Rajas, and Tamas.
From Sattvika-ahamkara evolves the mind, and the five
organs of knowledge (Jnanendriyas); from the
Rajasika-ahamkara, the five organs of action (Karmendriyas);
and from the Tamasika-ahamkara, the five elements (Bhutas) in their subtle and five in their gross aspects,
numbering ten. The subtle aspect of elements is called Tanmatra
or Bhutadi. These are sound (Shabda),
touch (Sparsha), form (Rupa),
taste (Rasa), and smell (Gandha). Out of these Tanmatras evolve the gross elements corresponding to each
of them in their respective order - Akasha (sky), Vayu (air), Agni (fire), Ap (water) and Prithvi
(earth). Unlike the earlier categories the gross elements are only evolutes and
not evolvements, since no new category comes out of them. These twenty-three besides
Prakriti constitute the twenty-four body-mind of embodied
Purushas and the universe they experience. The object
of the Samkhya is to impart wisdom by revealing the
distinctiveness of the Purusha, the twenty-fifth entity,
from these twenty-four objective categories.
Some Important Features of the Samkhya
There are a few important features in this Samkhyan
classification of categories deserving special attention. First,
Prakriti, the Objective Reality and the first category of the
Samkhya, can never be equated with the energy or matter of the modern
scientist. Matter is comparable only to the Bhutas,
the last category to evolve from a succession of earlier psychological categories
like Buddhi and Ahamkara.
Though evolutes of insentient Prakriti, these psychological
categories, being predominantly Sattvika, can reflect
the intelligence of the Purusha, and therefore appear
like conscious entities. But the last of the categories, the Bhutas
or material elements, are products of the Tamasa aspect
of Ahamkara and are therefore incapable of reflecting
intelligence. So they are called insentient matter, but unlike in the modern scientific
conception, this view of matter makes matter a product of psychological factors.
It is not matter that has evolved mind as some scientists think, but it is just
the reverse.
Secondly, in classical Samkhya, the analysis of Prakriti into categories does not seem to have much of
a cosmological significance. It is primarily soteriological,
i.e. salvation oriented. Prakriti functions for the
release of the Purusha. Man finds himself in suffering
because of his entanglement in the cycle of birth and death. This in turn is due
to the Purusha thinking of himself to be what he is
not. Linked with Prakriti by the Linga
Sharira (subtle body) he thinks himself to be
Prakriti and its evolutes, of which the body-mind is constituted. If
the Purusha is to understand what he is, he must first
know what he is not, i.e. this body-mind which he mistakenly thinks himself to be.
For he must first have an analytical knowledge of what he is not.
The analytical study of Prakriti and its evolutes is
undertaken by the Samkhya with the sole purpose of giving
man this salvation-giving knowledge. This knowledge is gained not by a mere intellectual
exercise. It has to become a basic discipline of the Buddhi
by which consciousness is able to empty itself
of every-thing that is not conscious. This is possible only for one whose conviction
in the painfulness and undesirability of life as constituted is total and who is
possessed of a deep and unremitting urge to get out of One may say that consciousness
without any content is emptiness or Shunyata, but it
is an emptiness that reveals everything, including the body-mind, in their separation.
A person who has attained to this intuitive apprehension may be in the body but
he is not of it. Says the Samkhya Karika:
‘Thus from the repeated study of the Truth, there results the wisdom, “I do not
exist, naught is mind. I am not”, which leaves no residue
(to be known), is pure, being free from ignorance and is absolute’ (64). On the
exhaustion of the quantum of Karma that has brought the body-mind into existence,
the Linga Sharira, that
links the Prakriti and Purusha,
is also destroyed.
The purpose of the evolution of Prakriti, which consists
in securing the release or isolation of the Purusha,
is thus fulfilled and Prakriti retires. Says the Kárika: ‘The work of Prakriti,
namely, the production of categories from intellect down to the gross elements,
is for the end of the release of each spirit;
this she does for another’s benefit (i.e. the Purusha’s),
as if it were her own’ (56). Having accomplished this, Prakriti
retires. As the Karika puts it: ‘As
a dancer desists from dancing, having exhibited herself to the audience, so does
Primal Nature (Prakriti) desist, having exhibited herself
to the spirit. It is my belief that there is not any other being more
bashful than Prakriti who, because of the realization
“I have been seen”, never again comes into the view of the spirit’ (Kàrika
56 & 61).
Thirdly, the classical Samkhya, though a spiritually
oriented system, is without any place for God, a Supreme Intelligence who is the
controller, the support, and origin of the whole universe. This appears to go counter
to most of the spiritually oriented world-views. The Samkhya
considers God a superfluous assumption lacking proof. A dynamic
Prakriti eternally existing with all effects involved in it (Satkarya-vada)
eliminates the need of an efficient and material cause in the form of an
Ishwara. The Purushas, the individual
centres of consciousness, and the purpose of providing him with experiences
that tend to liberate him ultimately, are sufficient to explain the intelligent
and purposive functioning of Prakriti. For attaining
liberation there is no need for the grace of an Ishwara
to intervene. The discriminative wisdom generated by the discipline of the system
alone can achieve this.
Pre-classical Samkhya
It is the recognition of the above version of Samkhya
philosophy by the great Vedantic Acharyas
like Shankara and the refutation of its atheism that
has made the student of Indian philosophy consider it as the Samkhya,
forgetting that it is only this classical version of the system of thought, which
has been the subject of Vedantic criticism. Modern research
has however revealed that the Samkhya had a long past
when it was indistinguishable from the Vedanta, The Vedic literature, and especially
the Upanishadic, has various seed thoughts and doctrines
as also terminologies without precise meanings. This provided the intellectual climate
required for the emergence of different systems of thought based on the same texts.
Basic terms of Indian philosophy like Brahman, Atman, Prakriti,
Akshara, etc. which came to have precise meanings in later philosophies,
had a long history in the early thought with developing meanings. Thus the clarified
and well-defined systems of philosophy like the Samkhya
and the Vedanta could have had their origins in the early Vedic thought, whose concepts
and terms conveying them assumed widely varying meanings with the development of
philosophic thinking.
The concepts of the Purusha, of the
Prakriti, of the Gunas, of the evolution
of different categories, of life being a vale of sorrows, of the doctrine of Samsara or repeated births and deaths, of gaining freedom
from Samsara through spiritual striving, etc. are familiar
to the Upanishads, may be with some differences of meaning and they find a place
in the classical Samkhya. The Mundaka
and the Katha Upanishads, if closely studied, will be
found to have much Samkhyan affinities. The
Shvetashvatara Upanishad gives clear evidence of the existence of a pre-classical
Samkhya that is not distinguishable from
Vedantic ideas. In that Upanishad we get for the first time the expression
Prakriti, which is also called Maya - a term which in
the earlier literatures was known as Brahman, Akshara,
Avyakta, and Mahan-atma.
The theory of the three Gunas, which bind the
Purusha, is adumbrated in this Upanishad in the passage IV.5, where it
speaks of the ‘Aja’ (‘female unborn’), red, white, and
black in colour, and producing offspring resembling
her. The dualism of Purusha and Prakriti
is clearly visible, but unlike in the classical Samkhya
they are unified in Supreme Being, all-powerful, described as Isha
or Deva. Prakriti is called
His Yoni (source of creative power) and also as Devatma-shakti
(the inherent Power of the Lord). It speaks in the same breath in contiguous passages
about Samkhya and Vedanta in expressions like
samkhya-yogadhigamyam (the Highest Truth that can be attained through
Samkhya and Yoga) and vedante
pracoditam paramam guhyam (the Supreme Truth inculcated in the Vedanta).
The Upanishad also mentions the name of Kapila, the
reputed author of the Samkhya philosophy, although that
word is interpreted in commentaries as the ‘golden-coloured
one’, the Hiranyagarbha.
Gita Samkhya
The existence of a pre-classical Samkhya, which is both
theistic and devotional and therefore indistinguishable from Vedanta, is most abundantly
clear from the Mahabharata from its most important sections, the Bhagavad-Gita,
and the Mokshadharma section of the
Shantiparva. Ever since the time of Shankaracharya
the Bhagavad-Gita has gained recognition as one of the most important
Vedantic texts - in fact as one of the three foundational
Vedantic texts (Prasthanatraya). But
critical scholars of the text today claim it also to be a pre-classical
Samkhyan text. It is interesting to note that Lord Krishna terms the
teaching he gives as Samkhya in several chapters. Thus
he calls his teaching as Samkhya in five places (cf.
11.39; 111.3; V.4-5; XIH.24; and XVIII. 13), while he refers to himself in a solitary
place as Vedantakrit or author of the Vedanta (cf. XV.15).
He repeatedly calls his teaching as Samkhya - an obnoxious
term in the contemporary philosophical context because of the reputation of the
system of that name for its uncompromising atheism, dualism, and realism. Even when
Krishna
names the Mimi Kapila as one of his
Vibhutis (glorious manifestations), Shankara
feels no hitch and goes ahead without any comment. But when he comes to the passage
‘procyate guna-samkhyane’
(‘it is said in the science enumerating the Gunas’,
cf. XVIIL19), he smells danger and remembers the real Samkhya,
his principal opponent (Pradhanamalla) in his commentary
on the Brahma-sutras. Considering this as a reference to Kapila’s
Samkhya system, he remarks: ‘This Shastra
(the Samkhya) is a valid source of knowledge about the
constituents or Gunas and the Jivas
who experience. Though it contradicts in respect of the nonduality
of the metaphysically Real or Brahman, the followers
of Kapila are adepts as regards constituents (Gunas)
and their operation’
The theory of the unaffected Atman discussed in the second chapter, which is one
of the basic teachings of the Gita, is described by
the Lord as Samkhya. The doctrine of the three Gunas and the various effects through which they are observed,
is perhaps discussed in greater detail here than in any Samkhyan
text proper. The distinction between the Purusha and
the Prakriti or Kshetrajna
and Kshetra, is described exactly as it is in the Samkhya texts. There is, however, one important difference.
While in classical Samkhya, Prakriti is
of the nature of the Gunas, the Gita
describes the Gunas both as constituting
Prakriti (Gunamayi), and as born of
Prakriti (Prakritijan). It is the power
of Ishwara (God).
The categories of Prakriti are reduced to eight in the
Gita in place of twenty-four. But all this is done with
some basic and fundamental differences from the classical Samkhya,
namely, that the Purusha and the Prakriti
are the higher and the lower aspects of the Power of Purushottama
(the Supreme Purusha), known jointly as the
Prakriti, and that the lower Prakriti has
power of creation only under the stimulation received from Purushottama,
and that the Jiva or the higher Prakriti
can gain release only by the grace of the Purushottama.
Thus it is found that a pre-classical Samkhya text like
the Gita is cent per cent theistic and devotional.
Epic Samkhya of the Mahabharata
The Mokshadharma of the Shantiparva
of the Mahabharata contains many details of what may be called pre-classical epic
Samkhya, which is theistic but yet
different from the Vedanta as also from the classical Samkhya.
Bhishma refers to Samkhya
as originated by Kapila, whom he calls an
Adhyatma-Chintaka, the founder of a spiritual doctrine. Like the classical
Samkhya it recognizes twenty-four categories of Prakriti, and the Purusha
as the twenty-fifth, but it differs from the former in holding, that there is no
ultimacy in the multiplicity of the twenty-fifth as
in the classical Samkhya. The Purusha,
in association with Prakriti in the creative cycle,
seems to be many. But in liberation, with the effacement of the bondage of Prakriti, the separateness of the Purusha
is effaced and it becomes the one and only Purusha that
exists in the nature of things. This version of Samkhya
too is sometimes called Anishwara (without a God), but
this is only in the sense that it does not have a twenty-sixth category called God
entirely distinct from the twenty-fifth, as was recognized by the
Yogins and the Gita-Samkhyans whose leanings
are towards the Vedanta.
It is interesting in this connection to note also the difference in the conception
of the Jiva between epic Samkhya
and the Gita Samkhya. The
Gita seems to speak in a divided voice regarding its
conception of the Jiva. In Chapter VII.4-5, the Lord
speaks of His Prakriti as having two expressions. The
first is the unconscious objective Prakriti called Apara (lower) which evolves into the eight categories
constituting the universe. The other called Para (higher) is what ‘becomes the Jiva’ (Jiva-bhuta). In what
appears to be a little different from this, in Chapter XV.7, he describes the Jiva as His own part (Amsha)
and not as an aspect of Prakriti. In
Samkhya proper, both epic and classical, Purusha
and Prakriti are entirely different categories
Another important respect in which the epic Samkhya
as also the Gita differs from classical
Samkhya is in that Prakriti in the former
cannot be active without the prompting or will of the Purusha.
The idea of a God is essential to them. But classical Samkhya,
as we have seen, makes dynamism inherent in the Prakriti
through the mechanism of the three Gunas.
Purusha has no operative part in it. He is only the witness and the enjoyer,
but never the actor. His presence has to be accepted because the
purposiveness of the evolution of Prakriti
cannot be explained otherwise. Prakriti functions in
order to liberate the Purusha ultimately from his entanglement
brought about by proximity to her. Classical Samkhya
scrupulously excludes a God as a superfluous and inconvenient assumption in their
way of thinking. Epic Samkhya, however, is entirely
different from it, in that the will of the Purusha is
necessary to make the Prakriti creative. But this Purusha of the epic Samkhya
is not Ishwara, a God, as accepted in the
Gita or in all schools of theism. Purusha,
free from bondage of Prakriti, is Ishwara,
but He becomes a limited centre of intelligence in bondage; He is therefore taken
only as the twenty-fifth category and not as the twenty-sixth. This equivocal position
of Ishwara in epic Samkhya
is one of the steps towards the emergence of atheistic Samkhya
of classical times.
Atheistic Theories of Panchashikha
The beginning of the atheistic doctrine into which Samkhya
developed in classical times can be found in the Mahabharata, Mokshadharma,
itself. The Samkhya philosophy traces its origin from
Kapila and its development through a succession of teachers
Aruni, Panchashikha, Asita-Devala, Varshaganya,
etc. to the classical statement of it in the Samkhya
Karika of Ishwarakrishna.
What all these teachers taught is not known, as none of them has left any work available
today. Ishwarakrishna’s Samkhya
Karika, which was produced between the 3rd and 5th century
A.D., is the first extant systematic work on the Samkhya
philosophy. It is claimed in it that there was an elaborate literature known as
Shashti-tantra on this system by the ancient teachers,
and that what Ishwarakrishna has given in the
Karika forms a summary of this. No such text as Shashti-tantra
is available now, and we have to presume that the Samkhya
developed into its later atheistic formulaion from its
Upanishadic and epic form in the course of the development
it underwent at the hands of these teachers. As for these teachers, we know nothing
of Kapila. The name is mentioned in the
Shvetashvatara Upanishad, but it is interpreted by commentators as the
Golden One or the Hiranyagarbha. The
Samkhya Sutras, otherwise known as Samkhya
Pravachana attributed to Kapila,
on which Vijnana Bhikshu
wrote a commentary in the sixteenth century, is a much later work originated probably
in the fifteenth century, as we find no ancient author referring to it anywhere
in their writings. From among these founding teachers of the Samkhya,
we get some idea of the trend of thought of Panchashikha
as set forth in Mokshadharma section of the
Shantiparva of the Mahabharata. We can see from it that he was one of
the main thinkers who gave an atheistic trend to Samkhya.
Panchashikha accepted a soul, the Purusha,
for accounting for man’s sense of a continuing ‘individuality, but the soul is not
in itself a conscious entity. Consciousness is a property that originates when the
Purusha comes into a conglomerated association with
the body-mind and Chetana or psychic efficiency, which
are parts of Avyakta or Prakriti,
the ultimate ground of the objective world. Being thus a product of the integration
of the Purusha with an aspect of Prakriti,
consciousness ceases at death. Man suffers because he identifies the
Purusha with the conglomeration of body-mind, and considers that conglomeration
to be his self. Mukti is got when this identification
ceases, and consciousness too ceases with it. The state of Mukti
is not one of ultimate destruction or of ultimate Reality. It is indeterminate and
indefinable. It cannot be iefinite1y described as a state of consciousness, as consciousness
is not an essential characteristic of the Purusha. In
bringing about these agglomerations called the body-mind or in identifying the Purusha with
such agglomerations, there is no need for a Purushottama
or God.
Probable Causes for Divergence from Vedanta
How and why the Samkhya differentiated itself from the
Vedanta and developed into an atheistic gospel is only a matter of guess. Religions,
including the Vedanta, base themselves on revealed Texts. Their data or fundamental
assumptions derive their validity from these Texts. The Vedanta no doubt gives an
important place for reasoning, but it-is mainly for elucidating these Texts and
bringing out a consistent meaning from them. Of course it is accepted that the scriptural
verities are ultimately verifiable through experience if one develops the insight
for the same. It is natural that all thinkers would not agree with this outlook
but would gradually drift towards reliance on reasoning. This must have happened
among the pre-classical Samkhyan thinkers of
India
also. They separated themselves from scripture- based Vedantins
into reason-based thinkers with only a loose scriptural affiliation. This is evident
from the very first two verses of Ishwarakrishna’s Samkhya Karika, which says:
‘From the experience of the threefold misery starts the enquiry after the means
of surmounting them. If it is said that such an enquiry is superfluous since they
can be erased by physically perceivable means, the answer is that this is not so,
as there is no certainty or finality in such means. Scriptural means too are inadequate
like the perceivable; for it is subject to impurity, destructibility, and
surpassability. Different from, and superior to it, there is the means
given by the discriminative knowledge of the evolved, the unevolved,
and the knower.’ This tendency to downgrade the importance of scripture must have
been responsible for the speculative theories of thinkers like
Panchashikha and the final termination in atheism. But the
Samkhya never rejected the Veda completely unlike the Buddhists and
the Jams and so continued to be included among the Astika
(orthodox) systems of thought. Besides, the Samkhya
brand of atheism never degenerated into the materialism of Charvakas,
hedonist, epicurians, and modern naturalists. It always
maintained spiritual and soteriological (salvation-oriented)
outlook.
Another influence that might have worked on the Samkhya
thinkers in this respect might have been the philosophical fashion set by the Buddhist
thinkers who developed a spiritual and ascetic view of life without a God or a soul,
which are the universal presumptions of all religions and spiritually oriented philosophies.
There are some people who cannot stand a theology, but yet find satisfaction only
in spirituality and asceticism. It was so then and it is so now too. The
Samkhya thinkers along with the Buddhists might have thought that the
inconsistencies in their position were not as bad as the inconsistencies in accepting
a God.
But Samkhya has continued to develop even after the
time of Ishwarakrishna and the criticism of the great
Vedantic Acharyas. In the
sixteenth century, in the writings of Vijnana
Bhikshu on the Samkhya Sutras, it abandoned
its atheism and aligned itself very largely with the Vedanta, And it is pointed
by Prof. S. S. Suryanarayana Sastri
in his Introduction to the translation of the Samkhya
Karika that a still later writer Mudumba
Narasimha Swami, in his unpublished writing named the
Samkhya-taru-vasanta, maintains that there is no radical
difference between the Samkhya and the Vedanta.
Bhagavata Samkhya
It is in this context that we get the Bhagavata Samkhya, that
forms the subject matter of Kapilopadesha. There are
several other brands too of Samkhya like that of Tattva-samasa, of Abirbudhanya
Samhita of the Pancharatra
school, of the Charaka Samhita, of the Buddha Charita,
and of Arada Kalama. Of all these, the
Bhagavata Samkhya is of special importance,
since it must have been an attempt to restore Samkhya,
which had become an atheistic gospel, into its pre-classical condition of a noble
spiritual philosophy akin to the Vedanta. The Bhagavata,
according to the modern scholarship, must have assumed its present form by the tenth
century and it is therefore quite reasonable to think that there is in it an attempt
to restore this ancient system of thought to its pristine devotional outlook. That
perhaps is the significance of putting these teachings into the mouth of
Kapila himself, reputed founder of the system, and is openly described
here as an Incarnation of Mahavishnu.
The doctrine is expounded in chapters 24-27 of the third Skandha
of the Bhagavata in the form of a conversation between
the s-age Kapila and his mother Devahuti.
It is apparently dualistic, at least with reference to the creative cycle, but it
is monistic when the cycle is over. The Purusha and
the Prakriti figure prominently in it as the two fundamental
categories. The former is eternal (Anadi), without the
Gunas of Prakriti (Nirgun), transcends Prakriti,
illumines everything (Pratyag Dharma), self-revealing
(Svayam Jyoti), and what
integrates everyhing (27.3). Though the
Purusha is recognized as transcending Prakriti
in verse 27.4, in the very next verse the latter is declared to be a power of the
Divine (Daivi) and constituted of the three
Gunas (Gunamayi) as distinct from
Purusha. It is called Pradhana (the principal
category), Avishesha (the indiscrete),
Avyakta (unclear), non-effect, Maya, etc. It is imperceptible but it
has to be accepted as existing eternally because it provides the basis of all effects,
and all distinctions are potential in it.
The Purusha on being casually approached by
Prakriti fecundates her by his sportive look. Prakriti
is thus stimulated to activity and produces innumerable bodies of wondrous type,
constituted of the Gunas. Seeing those creations of
Prakriti, the Purusha identifies
himself with these bodies and their transformations owing to loss of self-knowledge.
Because of this imaginative identification with the ‘other’ (parabhijnanena),
the Purusha falls into bondage. Though the
Purusha is in reality only the açtionless,
free, blissful, and uninvolved witness of the movements of Prakriti,
the imaginative identifications makes him feel himself to be the agent and enjoyer,
subject to Samsara and its consequent bondage and enslavement.
In this complex agent-enjoyer relationship the sense of agency together with the
cause and effect relationship is derived from Prakriti
whereas the sense of enjoyment of joy and sorrow is derived from the
Purusha who really transcends Prakriti.
Prakriti fecundated by the Purusha
evolves the twenty-four categories. The categories are as follows in the order of
succession: Mahat-tattva (also known as
Hiranyagarbha and Vasudeva) with
Chitta involved in it; Ahamkara having
Sattvika, Rajasika, and
Tamasika aspects; Manas
from the Sattvika, Buddhi
and the ten organs of knowledge and action from the Rajasika
and the five Tanmatras and their five gross effects
(Bhutas) from the Tamasika
aspect of Ahamkara.
There are some conspicuous differences in this from the enumeration of categories
in classical Samkhya: (1) Buddhi
here is only a sub-product of Ahamkara, (2)
Mahattattva takes the place of Buddhi as
the first of the evolutes, and (3) a category called Chitta
not differentiated from Mahattattva is also included
in the latter. This is said to be an aspect of Mahattattva
in the individual whereas Mahattattva as such is to
be considered cosmic.
In addition to these evolutes of Prakriti, an entirely
different category called Time is recognized in the Bhagavata
Samkhya. It is not an evolute
of Prakriti but the Shakti
or Power of Ishwara. It is Time that incites the dynamism
of Prakriti to take the form of Kalpa
(creative manifestation) and Pralaya (dissolution).
It is with the combination of the evolutes of Prakriti
of the nature of Gunas (Gunamayi)
that the cosmos well as the individual bodies are formed at the beginning of each
repetitive cycle of time, starting with Srishti (creation)
and ending with Pralaya (dissolution). These creations
of Prakriti are what cause identification and infatuation
in the Purusha and bring into being the transmigrating
Jiva.
The nature of the Jiva as the transmigrating Self is
not very clear. In classical Samkhya the
Purushas are countless in bondage and in liberation too, and have thus
each an eternal identity. In bondage, the Purusha is
in imaginative identification with the body-mind (Prakriti)
and in liberation this identification goes. Though, his multiplicity remains a fact,
he is alone (Kevala) in his own pristine nature. This
liberation from the bondage of Prakriti is got exclusively
through the discriminative intelligence generated by the Samkhyan
analysis of experience. There is no need of God’s grace, as there is no such being
in the classical Samkhya. But the position is different
in the Bhagavata Samkhya
and in the’ Gita Samkhya
as well. Following the doctrine as stated in the Kapilopadesha,
we have to presume that the Purusha in bondage is a
part of the Supreme Purusha (Purushottama)
as in the Gita, or a reflection of Him as in the classical
Advaita doctrine. This is not however clearly stated
in the text. As the teaching of Kapila is predominantly
devotional in spite of its Samkhya terminologies, we
have to presume that whatever be the source of Jiva
or Purusha, he is in bondage different from the Supreme
Being, Mahavishnu. But in liberation he becomes one
with Him, or if the Jiva prefers, remains an eternal
servant of God in realms of Light. Unlike in the Advaita,
bondage and liberation are real. Why and how bondage has come about is not attempted
to be explained beyond telling that the manifestations of the Gunas
of Prakriti infatuated the Purusha
by producing in him the suppression of knowledge. But it is clearly accepted that
liberation is possible and that it can be attained through devotion -
Bhakti, combined with.
knowledge or Jnana. It is stated that
by devotional pratices, the hook that binds the Jiva to Prakriti is dissolved
and then the bondage from Prakriti will never occur
again. This is given in answer to the objection of Devahuti
to the Samkhya theory that the Purusha
and Prakriti coexist eternally side by side in bondage
and in liberation. In that case liberation is impossible, and even if ratiocination
brings about release, the bondage of Prakriti cannot
be prevented from overtaking the Purusha again. Whether
Kapila’s answer that Bhakti
dissolves the ‘hook’ of bondage, and that the spiritual disciplines
practised by the body-mind will destroy that very body-mind just as fire
lit with a fuel destroys the very fuel, is adequate, remains an open question. Perhaps
no one can answer this ultimate question - how bondage came about and if it came
about once, could it not come again even after it has been overcome? The nearest
answer is what is given in the monistic doctrine which the Bhagavata
Samkhya seems to accept as the last resort. Though bound
in the state of ignorance, in liberation the individual spirit or the
Purusha is dissolved in the Purushottama,
the Supreme Being, and afterwards any question about that Purusha
returning becomes redundant.
It was pointed out that the classical Samkhya is more
soteriological than cosmological as also utterly non-theological.
But the Bhagavata Samkhya
is all these three, i.e. it is salvation oriented, it describes creation as a divine
act, and it teaches devotion to a personalized conception of the Supreme Being,
Mahavishnu. To elaborate upon the last point, it refers
to the Vaishnava theology of the Pancharatra
when it identifies Vasudeva as the Presiding Deity over
Mahattattva, Sankarshana
over Ahamkara,
and Aniruddha over Manas.
Pradyumna, one of the four Vyuhas,
is however omitted. The form of Mahavishnu as described
in the Vaishnava texts is placed before an aspirant
as the object of concentrated and devout meditation. The nine-limbed discipline
of Bhakti is advocated. Some of the best descriptions
of the genesis, development, and nature of Bhakti contained
in the Bhagavata occur in the 25th and in the 29th chapters
of this Skandha. Kapila,
the teacher of the Samkhya, is himself described as
an Incarnation of Mahavishnu.
Importance of Its Cosmological Theory
Its most significant deviation from classical Samkhya
consists in respect of its cosmological theories. The classical
Samkhya conceived Prakriti as inherently
dynamic with its alternating cyclic movement of Kalpa
(manifestation) and Pralaya (dissolution) each lasting
for aeons eternally. While the movement itself is self-
propelled, purposiveness is given to it by the presence
of the intelligent. Purushas by its side. Beyond describing the evolution of the twenty
three categories from it and giving a general statement that the worlds are formed
for the fruition of the Karmas of the Purushas, it does
not bother with cosmology.
But the Bhagavata Samkhya
outlook is in total disagreement with this. Prakriti
constituted of the Gunas is no doubt dynamic but its
dynamism is a capacity which can become effective only by the stimulation and energization derived from the will of the
Purushottama. Besides, Prakriti is not
an independent entity but a power of Ishwara. At every
stage of the creative process, the Bhagavata seeks to
invoke the will of the Purushottama in it. Thus refuting
the classical Samkhyan conception of an independent,
self- sufficient, and self-evolving Prakriti requiring
for its functioning no Directive Principle, a Purushottama,
both transcending Prakriti and immanent in it, is brought
into the cosmology of the Bhagavata
Samkhya.
This metaphysical idea diverting the Bhagavata Samkhya from the atheistic tone of its classical
prototype, is however hidden by the mythological language in which
it is clothed. The beginning of the creative cycle is thus described:
The all-pervading Being assumed in a sportive way His
own divine Prakriti approaching Him by chance, and then
Prakriti began producing numerous offspring of like
nature, wonderfully diverse according to the Gunas.
This initial movement of Prakriti is also described
as set in by Time, which is described as ‘the Bhagavan’s
inherent power manifest externally enfolding all beings’. It is also described as
a look of the Bhagavan which fecundates
Prakriti, i.e. makes its ‘capacities’ evolve and come into manifestation.
The evolution of the categories of Prakriti enumerated
before is then effected. The categories remain in disjunction and cannot combine
into the agglomerations that constitute the universe. Then the Supreme Being along
with Kala (Time), Karma, and the Gunas,
enters into them. Stimulated by the Lord, the Primordial Categories now combine
into the Cosmic Egg, which however remains inert. Then the Great Spirit pierces
the Self from within and brings out the various organs that form the
Virat Purusha (the Cosmic Man), but he remains
inert like a sleeping man. The functions of the various organs with their presiding
deities then enter their respective places but that cannot rouse the Cosmic Being.
Then the Chaitya (the Principle of sentiency) who is
the Kshetrajna (the Knower of the Field as
Jiva) enters and the Cosmic Being wakes up.
This mythological account is given in great detail in chapter 26. Its import is
that the Supreme Being, the Purushottama who transcends
Prakriti and at the same time indwells it, has to be
taken into account in the true Samkhya world-view, which
was perverted into an atheistic system in later times by the classical
Samkhyan thinkers. The Bhagavata
Purana, which according to modern scholarship assumed its present
form by around the tenth century, has worked various philosophical doctrines prevailing
at that time into a shape consistent with its devotional world-view. In
Kapilopadesha, one of the most brilliant sections of the
Purana, the ancient system of Kapila
is sought to be reconstructed as it was taught by its reputed author, who is depicted
as an Incarnation of Mahavishnu.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
1. Samkhya Karika of Ishwarakrishna,
edited and translated by S. S. S. Sastry,
University of
Madras.
2. The Samkhya System of A. B. Keith, ‘The Heritage
of
India
Series’.
3. Essays on Samkhya by Anima Sen
Gupta,
Patna
University
.
4. Samkhya and Advaita Vedanta
by G. H. Larson, M/s. Motilal Banarsidass.
5. Classical Samkhya by Anima Sen
Gupta,
Patna
University
.
6. Classical Samkhya by G. H. Larson, M/s.
Motilal Banarsidass.
7. Theism of Pre-classical Samkhya by Dr. K. B. Ramakrishna
Rao, University of
Mysore
.
(Extracted from the book Kapilopadesha in English by
Swami Tapasyananda of Advaita
Ashrama (Publication Department) 5,
Dehi Entally Road, Calcutta-700 014)